Susan Stebbing's Intellectualism
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.15173/jhap.v10i4.4829Abstract
This paper reconstructs Susan Stebbing’s account of intelligent
dealing with a problem and defends this account against charges
that it relies on a “censurable kind” of intellectualism. This charge
was made in Stebbing’s own time by Laird and Wittgenstein. Michael
Kremer has recently made the case that Stebbing is also a proximate
target of Gilbert Ryle’s attack on intellectualism. This paper argues
that Stebbing should indeed be counted as an intellectualist since she
holds that intelligent dealing with a problem requires propositional
thought. Yet, for Stebbing, thinking is an activity of a whole person
and is enabled and constrained by their dispositions. This complex
picture of a thinker enables Stebbing’s account to resist arguments
targeting certain forms of intellectualism such as Ryle’s regress
argument. It also helps her to respond to the charge that she
overemphasizes the importance of intellectual failures. On the picture
that emerges, Stebbing offers a strikingly modern epistemology that
incorporates the social features of a person as well as their purely
intellectual features.
References
Aristotelian Society, ed., 1948. Philosophical Studies. London: G. Allen & Unwin.
Beaney, Michael and Siobhan Chapman, 2017. “Susan Stebbing.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Summer 2017, edited by Edward N. Zalta. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Bengson, John and Marc A. Moffett, 2011. “Two Conceptions of Mind and Action: Knowledge How and the Philosophical Theory of Intelligence.” In Knowing How: Essays on Knowledge, Mind, and Action, edited by John Bengson and Marc Moffett, pp. 3–55. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bradley, F. H., 1904. “On Truth and Practice.” Mind 13(51): 309–35.
Chapman, Siobhan, 2013. Susan Stebbing and the Language of Common Sense. New York: Springer.
Dewey, John, 1910. How We Think. Boston: D. C. Heath & Co.
———, 1938. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. New York: Henry Holt and Company.
Douglas, Alexander X. and Jonathan Nassim, 2021. “Susan Stebbing’s Logical Interventionism.” History and Philosophy of Logic 0: 1–17.
Forster, E. M., 1940. “Review of Virginia Woolf: the Critical Heritage.” New Statesman and Nation 10 August 1940 (accessed at ProQuest One Literature on 18 January 2022): 140–41.
Gerwarth, R., 2016. The Vanquished: Why the First World War Failed to End, 1917-1923. London: Penguin Books Limited.
Habgood-Coote, Joshua, 2019. “Knowledge-How, Abilities, and Questions.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97(1): 86–104.
Hickman, N. Waights, 2019. “Knowing in the “Executive Way”: Knowing How, Rules, Methods, Principles and Criteria.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 99(2): 311–35.
Judt, T., 2011. Postwar: A History of Europe Since 1945. London: Random House.
Kremer, Michael, forthcoming. “Margaret MacDonald and Gilbert Ryle: A Philosophical Friendship.” British Journal for the History of Philosophy: 1–24.
———, 2017a. “A Capacity to Get Things Right: Gilbert Ryle on Knowledge.” European Journal of Philosophy 25(1): 25–46.
———, 2017b. “Ryle’s “Intellectualist Legend” in Historical Context.” Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 5(5).
Laird, J., 1942. “Stebbing, L. S. -Ideals and Illusions.” Mind 51: 194.
———, 1948. “Reflections Occasioned by Ideals and Illusions.” In Aristotelian Society (1948), pp. 20–30.
Lorimer, E. O., 1939. What Hitler Wants. London: Penguin Books.
Ryle, Gilbert, 1939. “Conscience and Moral Convictions.” Analysis 7(2): 31–39.
———, 1945. “Knowing How and Knowing That: The Presidential Address.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46: 1–16.
———, 1949/2009. The Concept of Mind. London: Routledge.
———, 1968. “Thinking and Reflecting.” Royal Institute of Philosophy Lectures 1: 210–26.
———, 1971. “Thinking and Self-Teaching.” Journal of Philosophy of Education 5(2): 216–28.
Sait, Una Bernard, 1916. “Stebbing’s Pragmatism and French Voluntarism.” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 13(8): 219.
Schiller, F. C. S., 1912. “The ‘Working’ of ‘Truths’.” Mind 21(84): 532–35.
———, 1913. “The ‘Working’ of Truths and Their ‘Criterion’.” Mind 22(88): 532–38.
Snyder, T., 2011. Bloodlands: Europe between Hitler and Stalin. London: Random House.
Stanley, Jason, 2011. Know How. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stebbing, L. Susan, 1913. “The ‘Working’ of ‘Truths’.” Mind 22(86): 250–53.
———, 1914. Pragmatism and French Voluntarism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———, 1930/1948. A Modern Introduction to Logic. London: Methuen & Co.
———, 1934. Logic in Practice. London: Methuen & Co.
———, 1937/1944. Philosophy and the Physicists. Middlesex: Penguin Books.
———, 1939/1941. Thinking to Some Purpose. New York: NY: Allen Lane: Penguin Books.
———, 1941/1948. Ideals and Illusions. London: Watts & Co.
———, 1943/1961. A Modern Elementary Logic. London: Methuen.
———, 1944. “Men and Moral Principles.” L. T. Hobhouse Memorial Trust Lectures 13.
Thouless, Robert, 1930/1953. Straight and Crooked Thinking. London: Pan Books Ltd.
Weatherson, Brian, 2017. “Intellectual Skill and the Rylean Regress.” Philosophical Quarterly 67(267): 370–86.
Wilson, John Cook, 1926. Statement and Inference. London: Oxford University Press.
Wisdom, John, 1934. Problems of Mind and Matter. London: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, Rush Rhees and Gabriel Citron, 2015. “Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Conversations with Rush Rhees (1939–50): From the Notes of Rush Rhees.” Mind 124(493): 1–71.
Downloads
Published
Issue
Section
License
The Public Knowledge Project recommends the use of the Creative Commons license. The Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy requires authors to agree to a Creative Commons Attribution /Non-commercial license. Authors who publish with the Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy agree to the following terms:
- Authors retain copyright and grant the journal right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons BY-NC license.
- Authors are able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the non-exclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), with an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal.
- Authors are permitted and encouraged to post their work online (e.g., in institutional repositories or on their website) prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (See The Effect of Open Access)
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License.