Crude Meaning, Brute Thought (or: What Are They Thinking?!)
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.15173/jhap.v7i2.3483Abstract
I address here the question what sense to make of the idea that there can be thought prior to language (both in ontogeny and among nonlinguistic animals). I begin by juxtaposing two familiar and influential philosophical views, one associated with the work of Paul Grice, the other associated with the work of Donald Davidson. Grice and Davidson share a broad, rationalist perspective on language and thought, but they endorse conflicting theses on the relation between them. Whereas, for Grice, thought of an especially complex sort is a precondition of linguistic meaning, for Davidson, there can be no genuine thought without language. I argue that both views present us with unpalatable alternatives concerning our understanding of the natural origins of objective thought and meaningful language. Drawing on what I take to be key insights from Grice and Davidson, I then lay out some broad desiderata for an intermediate position. I finally turn to a certain form of nonlinguistic communication of the sort of which both prelinguistic children and languageless animals are capable, viz., expressive communication. I propose that a proper appreciation of the character and function of expressive communication can help us trace the outlines of the desired intermediate position.
References
———, 1994. “Conceptual Relativism and Translation.” In Language, Mind and Epistemology: On Donald Davidson’s Philosophy, edited by G. Preyer, F. Siebelt, and A. Ulfig, pp. 145–70. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
———, 1995. “Reconstructing ‘Meaning’: Grice and the Naturalization of Semantics.” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 76: 83–116.
———, 2004. Speaking My Mind: Expression and Self-Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
———, 2010. “Expressing as ‘Showing What’s Within’.” Philosophical Books 51: 212–27.
———, 2013a. “Expressive Communication and Continuity Skepticism.” The Journal of Philosophy 110: 293–330.
———, 2013b. “Origins of Meaning: Must We ‘Go Gricean’ ?” Mind & Language 28: 342–75.
———, 2015. “Expression: Acts, Products, and Meaning.” In Meaning Without Representation: Essays on Truth, Expression, Normativity, and Naturalism, edited by S. Gross, N. Tebben and M. Williams, pp. 180–209. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———, 2016. “Sociality, Expression, and This Thing Called Language.” Inquiry 59: 56–79.
———, 2017. “Communicative Intentions, Expressive Communication, and Origins of Meaning.” In Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Animal Minds, edited by K. Andrews and J. Beck, pp. 301–12. London: Routledge.
———, 2018. “Minding the Gap: In Defense of Mind–mind Continuity.” In Wittgenstein and Naturalism, edited by K. Cahill and T. Raleigh, pp. 177–203. New York: Routledge.
Bar-On, Dorit and Mitchell S. Green, 2010. “Lionspeak: Communication, Expression and Meaning.” In Self, Language and Word: Problems from Kant, Sellars and Rosenberg, edited by J. O’Shea and E. Rubenstein, pp. 89–106. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
Bar-On, Dorit and Matthew Priselac, 2011. “Triangulation and the Beasts.” In Triangulation: From an Epistemological Point of View, edited by C. Amoretti and G. Preyer, pp. 121–52. New York: Oxford University Press.
Beck, Jacob, 2012. “Do Animals Engage in Conceptual Thought?” Philosophy Compass 7: 218–29.
———, 2013. “Why We Can’t Say What Animals Think.” Philosophical Psychology 26: 520–46.
Bermudez, José Luis, 2003. Thinking Without Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Berwick, Robert C. and Noam Chomsky, 2016. Why Only Us: Language and Evolution. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Brandom, Robert B., 1994. Making it Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Burge, Tyler, 2010a. Origins of Objectivity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———, 2010b. “Steps Toward Origins of Propositional Thought.” Disputato 4: 39–67.
Campbell, John, 2011. Review of Tyler Burge, Origins of Objectivity. The Journal of Philosophy 108: 269–85.
Carruthers, Peter, 2009. “Invertebrate Concepts Meet the Generality Constraint (and Win).” In The Philosophy of Animal Minds, edited by R. Lurz, pp. 89–107. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Cheney, Dorothy and Robert M. Seyfarth, 2003. “Signalers and Receivers in Animal Communication.” Annual Review of Psychology 54: 145–73.
———, 2007. Baboon Metaphysics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Clark, Andy, 2006. “Language, Embodiment and the Cognitive Niche.” TRENDS in Cognitive Sciences 10: 370–74.
Cussins, Adrian, 1990. “Content, Conceptual Content, and Nonconceptual Content.” In The Philosophy of Artificial Intelligence, edited by M. Boden, pp. 380–400. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Darwin, Charles, 1872. The Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals. London: John Murray.
Davidson, Donald, 1974. “Belief and the Basis of Meaning.” Synthese 27: 309–23.
———, 1994. “The Social Aspect of Language.” In The Philosophy of Michael Dummett, edited by B. McGuiness and G. Oliveri, pp. 1–16. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
———, 1999. “The Emergence of Thought.” Reprinted in Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective, pp. 123–34. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2001.
Dretske, Fred L., 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
Dummett, Michael, 1993. Origins of Analytical Philosophy. London: Duckworth.
Fodor, Jerry A., 1975. The Language of Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Gauker, Christopher, 2011. Words and Images: An Essay on the Origin of Ideas. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Green, Mitchell S., 2007. Self-Expression. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Grice, H. P., 1957. “Meaning.” Philosophical Review 66: 377–88.
———, 1982. “Meaning Revisited.” Reprinted in Studies in the Way of Words, pp. 283–303. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Hurford, James R., 2007. The Origins of Meaning: Language in the Light of Evolution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hutto, Daniel D., 2008. Folk Psychological Narratives: The Socio-Cultural Basis of Understanding Reasons. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
Hutto, Daniel D. and Erik Myin, 2013. Radicalizing Enactivism: Basic Minds Without Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———, 2017. Evolving Enactivism: Basic Minds Meet Content. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Hutto, Daniel D. and Glenda Satne, 2017. “Continuity Scepticism in Doubt: A Radically Enactive Take.” In Embodiment, Enaction, and Culture: Investigating the Constitution of the Shared World, edited by C. Durt, T. Fuchs and C. Tewes, pp. 107–27. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Lepore, Ernest and Kirk Ludwig, 2005. Donald Davidson: Meaning, Truth, Language, and Reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lycan, William G., 1996. Consciousness and Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Malcolm, Norman, 1973. “Thoughtless Brutes.” Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 46: 5–20.
Manser, Marta B., 2001. “The Acoustic Structures of Suricates’ Alarm Calls Varies with Predator Type and the Level of Response Urgency.” Proceedings of the Royal Society, series B, Biological Sciences 268: 2315–24.
McDowell, John, 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Millikan, Ruth, 1984. Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories. Cambridge, MA: Bradford Books/MIT Press.
———, 1996. “Pushmi-Pullu Representations.” In Philosophical Perspectives, vol. 9, AI, Connectionism, and Philosophical Psychology, edited by J. Tomberlin, pp. 185–200. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.
———, 2004a. “On Reading Signs: Some Differences Between Us and the Others.” In Evolution of Communication Systems: A Comparative Approach, edited by D. Oller and U. Griebel, pp. 15–30. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———, 2004b. Varieties of Meaning: The 2002 Jean Nicod Lectures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Origgi, Gloria and Dan Sperber, 2000. “Evolution, Communication, and the Proper Function of Language.” In Evolution and the Human Mind: Modularity, Language, and Meta-Cognition, edited by P. Carruthers and A. Chamberlain, pp. 140–69. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rosenberg, Jay F., 2007. Wilfrid Sellars: Fusing the Images. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schiffer, Stephen R., 1972. Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Scott-Phillips, Thom, 2014. Speaking Our Minds: Why Human Communication is Different, and How Language Evolved to Make it Special. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Sellars, Wilfrid, 1969. “Language as Thought and as Communication.” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 29: 506–27.
Sias, James and Dorit Bar-On, 2015. “Emotions and Their Expressions.” In Emotional Expression, edited by C. Abell and J. Smith, pp. 46–72. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tormey, Alan, 1971. The Concept of Expression. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Downloads
Published
Issue
Section
License
The Public Knowledge Project recommends the use of the Creative Commons license. The Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy requires authors to agree to a Creative Commons Attribution /Non-commercial license. Authors who publish with the Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy agree to the following terms:
- Authors retain copyright and grant the journal right of first publication with the work simultaneously licensed under a Creative Commons BY-NC license.
- Authors are able to enter into separate, additional contractual arrangements for the non-exclusive distribution of the journal's published version of the work (e.g., post it to an institutional repository or publish it in a book), with an acknowledgement of its initial publication in this journal.
- Authors are permitted and encouraged to post their work online (e.g., in institutional repositories or on their website) prior to and during the submission process, as it can lead to productive exchanges, as well as earlier and greater citation of published work (See The Effect of Open Access)
This work is licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution-NonCommercial 3.0 Unported License.